Monday, February 28, 2011

Marx and Hobbes would have gotten in a bar fight

Marx – for all his gloom and doom about loss of identity through forced labor – was something of a disgusting optimist. In Marx’s view, people are caught in a system of “forced labor. It is therefore not the satisfaction of a need; it is merely a means to satisfy needs external to it” (655). Thus people are currently producing not because they need the product, but because they need the financial value associated with that product. In this system, Marx argues that the identity and the worth of the worker is lost as “the worker puts his life into the object…now his life no longer belongs to him by to the object” (652). So far, Marx seems to have a pretty pessimistic outlook on the way the world works. But then we get t his solution to the problem: A “community of free individuals” (669). And that’s where Marx goes off on an overly optimistic jaunt through Never Never Land.

First off, let’s start with the notion of a “community free individuals.” “Community” implies at the very least a relationship in which people are functioning together, which it itself limits total independence. A community requires some sort of compromise in order for it to function as a unit, thus an entirely free individual wouldn’t actually be a functioning member of the community (they would just be functioning as themselves while surrounded by a community, but they would not be part of said community). Thus both the “free” and the “individual” get diminished, and Marx got off to a rather bad start by creating an oxymoron right off the bat.

Moving deeper into Marx’s theory on this community, Marx proves to have overly optimistic view of human nature. In this community, he sees people as recreating the lifestyle of Robinson Crusoe, and the “characteristics of Robinson’s labour are here repeated, but with this difference, that they are social, instead of individual’ (669). Applying Robinson Crusoe’s model – which is the extreme example of the individual producing only for himself – to an entire community simply cannot work. Production for self is never the same as production for everyone, particularly when a system of allotment of goods is put in place, as Marx does. Robinson Crusoe yielded exactly what he built/grew/created/etc, but someone in Marx’s society would still be receiving an abstract value in response to his or her labor. Marx talks about how the community will labor together to supply itself with its needs, and Marx throws in the idea that each man will receive according to his needs in proportion to the amount of work done. Where on earth does Marx get the idea that people will be indefinitely content under this system, or even that any sort of agreement could be reached? The notion of “the share of each individual producer in the means of subsistence is determined by his labour-time” could only work if all labor was the same, but obviously it’s not (669). Eight hours of laboring at a computer as an accountant is entirely different from eight hours of laboring with a sledgehammer as a construction worker. Marx seems to think people could actually agree on what the value of the eight hours of the accountant vs. the eight hours as a construction worker would be worth, and that people would be willing to be distributed to accordingly. Doubtful. And what about those who cannot labor effectively? In Marx’s world, cripples, the disabled, or the simply inept would have to be promptly drummed out of the society in order for this system to continuing functioning.

Then there comes the issue of “the total product of [the] community is a social product” (669). And the issue with that is simply that people aren’t always too keen on sharing. Call it survival instinct, call it selfish, call it just plain normal, after laboring for eight hours a day on a product, the thought of sacrificing it to a common social good isn’t always be a pleasant thought. And what happens if those eight hours are valued at less of a “labour-time” ratio than someone else, and all the efforts of that product yield a small portion value when it comes time for distribution? In some cases, it would then make more sense to keep the product. And in that case, the individual would either remain a dissatisfied member of the community or leave it, and either way, the society has proven to be dysfunctional and failed.

And speaking of products, that brings me to my biggest issue with Marx’s theory, and that is that it is still reductive. Even under this model, people are still only worth what they can produce. Because the “distribution of portion” is based on labour-time, the value is still placed on production (669). How is a person working for “distribution” any different from them working for monetary gain in the capitalist system? The capacity for production is still the dominating factor, shared or not.

Thus while Marx does a good job focusing on the problems in his society, he does a pretty poor job when it comes to his solution. He shifts from his condemnation of the current human condition to an excessively optimistic vision of human nature, and his vision is not conducive to creating a real solution with real individuals. Similar to Percy Bysshe Shelley’s frantic calls for revolution and change, Marx loves pointing out what’s wrong but forgets to suggest how it can be (realistically) fixed.

3 comments:

  1. Aubrey,

    So, in response to your critique of Marx' community, here's a question for you. First, I would argue that his idea of distribution based on labour-time is not limited to the actual time put in, or the value of the work, but also the consumption of the community. He says that "it also serves as a measure of the portion of the common labour borne by each individual, and of his share in the part of the total product destined for individual consumption" (669). I may be reading this wrong, but I thought this was meant as a measurement of his contribution. Therefore, while the value of the commodity would be considered, the fact that the commodity is used by the community is also considered.

    Second, this idea of community keeps making me think of the church in Acts. Acts 4 says "And the congregation of those who believed were of one heart and soul; and not one of them claimed that anything belonging to him was his own; but all things were common property to them" (Acts 4:32). I don't know that it's identical to Marx theory, but it rings similar, and while I know Marx didn't think too highly of the church, it just strikes me that here in fact is a community where everything was put together "and they would be distributed to each, as any had need" (Acts 4:35). While Marx is focused on a more rigid understanding of "need" I still see the correlation of communities that come and work together for the good of the entire community.

    ReplyDelete
  2. Nat,

    I think that you might be right, and that Marx is referring to the total product, but I still think he is way too idealistic to think that we could ever all agree on the value of that product produced, or how necessary it is. Going back to my original example of the accountant and the construction worker (even though neither existed in Marx's day), how do we even begin to compare the products of their labor? How do we value one over the other? And this still brings us back to the problem of valuing the PRODUCT, not the person, and that is what Marx preaches against in the capitalist system. So I guess my biggest problem with Marx is that he doesn't solve anything in his ideal community, but just changes the faces of the problems.
    In response to your ideas on Acts, I would say that yes, Marx is some ways seems to mimic these ideas of the ideal church community. What I find interesting about that is that, in the community you mentioned in Acts, the idea is the "one heart and soul," and thus it is a spiritual and emotional investment. Under that system,with God as the head, there is a kind of moral code that helps to support this notion of all working together and having the "common property." Marx doesn't have this same moral code in his community, but rather he's hoping that people will just naturally act that way. Hence my argument that Hobbes and Marx would go at it, because Marx seems incredibly optimistic about the basis of human nature in this. I just wonder how Marx reconciles the fact that this same "human nature" is the one that created the capitalist system and the one that dehumanizes people into mere product producers rather than humans and so forth and so on. So why would he think that people can be placed in a community together and naturally feel the desire to share and work for the benefit of everyone instead of just themselves?

    ReplyDelete
  3. I was comparing you ideas Aubrey to what we've been studying in Core 350, and I found it interesting when considering the concepts of constrained or unconstrained beings. Marx in many ways views humanity as unconstrained and able to rise above its societal sins, where as you seem to be skeptical and noting the respectable (and reformed) ideology that humans can never rise to any of because we are held back by human nature. While this perfectly well with you response to Natalie and initial argument, do you that this product/worker worth is the same tied to religion in general? I'm not sure I agree with you distinction between spiritual and emotional investment.

    ReplyDelete